U.S. Intellectual History Blog

Full Employment and “New Deal Liberalism”

o'connorThe following is a guest post from Mike O’Connor (the fifth of a series–see the first post here, the second here, the third here, and the fourth here). Mike is one of the original USIH bloggers and a founder of the Society for U.S. Intellectual History. He is the author of A Commercial Republic: America’s Enduring Debate over Democratic Capitalism, which will be published in May by the University Press of Kansas. The book’s Facebook page can be found here, and information from the publisher is available here.

American politicians, particularly presidents, fear the electoral consequences of high unemployment. The jobless occupy a space of constant anxiety; if allowed to continue, this unease will grow to envelop their families and friends before spreading to other workers and, eventually, the public at large. The desire for relief can manifest itself in support for anyone who can promise a radical change in the country’s economic direction. From the voter’s perspective, however, this behavior rests on a rather peculiar premise: that securing employment for the largest possible number of citizens is a federal responsibility. Nothing in our Constitution tasks the government with this duty or gives to it adequate powers to take on such an obligation. Moreover, a job represents a private arrangement between an employer and an employee, and it is hardly obvious that ensuring one for all workers should be a federal concern. The government promotes many things that it presumes to be good—like, say, healthy eating habits—without making them the centerpiece of domestic policy. What is different about jobs?

Like so much about American political economy, the answer to this philosophical question is rooted in history rather than theory. Until the end of the nineteenth century, the idea of a government employment policy would have struck many in the United States as nonsensical. A sizeable majority of Americans lived in rural areas and worked in agriculture, and wage labor was not particularly common. But industrialism reshaped both the city and the farm, and before too long a young adult who had grown up in a rural area had little choice but to leave it behind.

The break with traditional patterns of life prompted the rise of Progressivism. Among the central tenets of this movement was the belief that old ideas were unlikely to address new conditions adequately. One of the most influential Progressive thinkers, Herbert Croly, embodied this principle when he criticized the laissez faire orthodoxy of the Gilded Age. In the new industrial age, he argued, government economic intervention was no longer possible to avoid. Certainly, when the state “interferes,” it restricts the free play of economic forces. But if it “remains impartial,” government is actively deciding to allow “natural selection” to determine economic results. In either case, Croly concluded, the state “authorizes discriminations” by pursuing policies “which in their effect violate the doctrine of ‘equal rights.’” If government cannot help but intervene in the economy, he concluded, then it might as well attempt to maximize those things of which it approves.

Progressivism provided the intellectual point of departure that paved the way for modern-day liberalism. But it was the Great Depression, rather than some philosophical insight, that activated the federal commitment to fighting unemployment. This new government charge represented less a theoretical development than a political necessity: the extreme rates of joblessness (peaking at 24% in 1933) presented a problem that simply had to be solved. It is, therefore, a difficult task to tease out the intellectual constructions that justified the assigning of responsibility for unemployment to the federal government. Franklin Roosevelt frequently used the language of the new liberalism in suggesting that the industrial economy called for a complete rethinking of traditional American political values, as when he stated as a candidate in 1932 that “equality of opportunity as we have known it no longer exists.” (Much later, the notions of “Freedom from Want” and the “Economic Bill of Rights” would suggest similar commitments.) But his call for “bold, persistent experimentation,” which more closely described his behavior as president, implicitly rejected any overarching theoretical commitment. Indeed, Richard Hofstadter went so far as to claim that when “the federal government [assumed] primary responsibility for the relief of the unemployed” during the New Deal, “nothing revolutionary was intended.” The new charge, he asserted, was “simply a matter of politics.”

More recent historians have backed away from this extreme characterization. Alan Brinkley’s End of Reform, for example, did not argue that the New Deal represented no philosophy at all. But Brinkley pointed out that the commonly used phrase New Deal liberalism presupposes a unity of outlook that did not exist. Those who served in the Roosevelt administration expressed competing views about the nature of the problems facing the country, the best solutions to them, and the appropriate long-term adjustments to the relationship between the federal government and the nation’s economy. When Americans today invoke the philosophy of the New Deal, they tend to have in mind the particular approach—Keynesianism—that emerged only after a long period of struggle. Moreover, this strategy itself represented a compromise of sorts, Brinkley argued, in that it allowed the “state [to] manage the economy without managing the institutions of the economy.”

Within the administration, the Keynesian perspective on unemployment was embodied most clearly by Henry Wallace. Called by Louis Hartz “the most articulate and reflective of the New Dealers,” Wallace served as secretary of agriculture under FDR before being elected vice president in 1940. Though Roosevelt dropped him from the ticket in 1944, Wallace remained a supporter of the president. His 1945 book Sixty Million Jobs, written after FDR’s death when Wallace was Truman’s secretary of commerce, represented one of the more rigorous attempts to articulate the premises and policies that expressed the New Deal commitment to full employment. “It is also,” declared the economist assessing the book in the liberal Saturday Review, a “passionate statement of a remarkable American’s basic political, social and personal philosophy.”

The specific policy approach touted by Sixty Million Jobs was anchored by what Wallace called a “national budget.” Under this scenario, the president would submit a fiscal estimate that expressed for the coming year not only the anticipated spending of the government, but also the economic conditions that would characterize the private sector. Upon comparing the two to ideal models and assessing the difference between the projection and the desired outcome, the president would propose additional taxes, programs or expenditures whose purposes would be to provide a job for all who wanted one. (One available option would always be direct government employment.) Such an approach, Wallace argued, would have represented an official commitment to what Americans had come to expect implicitly and informally. Noting a significant barrier to the plan, he expressed concern over the tendency of the electorate to blame the government during bad times but to refuse to allow it to regulate the economy when things are going well. In the wake of the worst economic catastrophe in our history, Wallace asked whether it can be “now conceded” that “the cost of salvage, of cleaning up the wreckage from boom and depression,” is “so great that government should be asked to prevent some of the destruction from ever occurring?” His argument for government economic intervention in the employment market concluded with the point that “the people of this country, speaking through their elected representatives in Congress, must write that responsibility into law.”

Wallace was active in pushing for such legislation, and his work with lawmakers led to the Employment Act of 1946. Congressional sausage-making stripped the measure of its most forceful provisions, however, and the resulting law was all but toothless. In 1978, a similar fate befell another full employment bill: the Humphrey-Hawkins Act. Thus it is that the philosophy animating government economic intervention today remains similar to what Wallace described in 1945: the electorate demands that the government address high unemployment while refusing to it the tools for meaningfully confronting the problem.

5 Thoughts on this Post

S-USIH Comment Policy

We ask that those who participate in the discussions generated in the Comments section do so with the same decorum as they would in any other academic setting or context. Since the USIH bloggers write under our real names, we would prefer that our commenters also identify themselves by their real name. As our primary goal is to stimulate and engage in fruitful and productive discussion, ad hominem attacks (personal or professional), unnecessary insults, and/or mean-spiritedness have no place in the USIH Blog’s Comments section. Therefore, we reserve the right to remove any comments that contain any of the above and/or are not intended to further the discussion of the topic of the post. We welcome suggestions for corrections to any of our posts. As the official blog of the Society of US Intellectual History, we hope to foster a diverse community of scholars and readers who engage with one another in discussions of US intellectual history, broadly understood.

  1. While I have nothing of interest to say about (and would not quibble with) the history sketched here, and while it is true that prevailing (historical and contemporary) interpretations (especially libertarian, ‘originalist,’ and liberal ‘negative liberties’ views) of the Constitution would indeed conclude that “[n]othing in [it] tasks the government with [the] duty or gives to it adequate powers to” “secur[e] employment for the largest possible number of citizens,” there are any number of arguments among some of today’s legal theorists of the Constitution which proffer robust reasons for concluding that this could and, more importantly, should be an obligation of the federal government, given a proper understanding and interpretation of the U.S. Constitution. I will list only four titles as well representative of such arguments (which are distinct from each other even if sharing some premises): Sotirios A. Barber, Welfare and the Constitution (Princeton University Press, 2003); Alan Brudner, Constitutional Goods (Oxford University Press, 2004) James E. Fleming, Securing Constitutional Democracy: The Case of Autonomy (University of Chicago Press, 2006); and Lawrence G. Sager, Justice in Plainclothes: A Theory of American Constitutional Practice (Yale University Press, 2004). Sager provides perhaps the most “indirect” argument of the group, based as it is on the notion of a “constitutional division of labor” and an important distinction between the “adjudicated Constitution” and “the full Constitution,” allowing us to see precisely how and why there has been such a “durable gap between constitutional case law and political [including socio-economic] justice,” as well as appreciate the extent to which “adjudication does not exhaust the authoritative reach of the Constitution.” Again, while I’m most familiar with the above books, there are others that fit the bill as well. I suspect in a different (more propitious) political and cultural climate, arguments such as these will gain a wider and far more sympathetic hearing and thus “the philosophy animating government intervention” may be significantly if not radically revised in a more ambitious democratic direction.

    • Patrick:

      I am certainly not a legal scholar, and consequently should refrain from making offhand comments about the meaning of the Constitution. Thanks for introducing me and our readers to this strain of Constitutional interpretation.

      Mike

      • Mike,

        Just for the record, and lest anyone infer otherwise, I too am not at all a legal scholar, but happen to have an amateur’s (in the older sense of that term) ardent interest in a few topics in legal theory and philosophy of law, including constitutionalism (U.S. and ‘comparative’). In fact, I’m hardly a true scholar of anything whatsoever, but (for better or worse) possess the chutzpah or temerity to speak to matters about which I have a least some familiarity owing to a voracious but indiscriminate (disciplinarily speaking) reading appetite (e.g., you and your fellow contributors to this blog are far more knowledgeable on historical matters than I will ever be).

    • Thanks, Mark!

      Smith’s book makes points to which I am sympathetic, and it is a very impressive work of scholarship. But his focus is a little bit different than mine, so it didn’t come up much in my own work. I mentioned Building New Deal Liberalism briefly in my book, mostly to emphasize the incredible scale of public works programs taken on by the New Deal. So if by “engage the arguments of” you mean “cite in support of a point I was making,” then the answer is “Yes, I did!”

Comments are closed.