U.S. Intellectual History Blog

The Reformism of Fear

Courtesy of Amazon

Two of the most famous aphorisms attesting to a “pessimism of the intellect/optimism of the will” mentality are, “Power concedes nothing without a demand” (Frederick Douglass), and “The master’s tools will never dismantle the master’s house” (Audre Lorde). On the one hand, these two sentences promise that change only comes out of a struggle with an entrenched and stubborn enemy—a promise that naturally might lead to some pessimism. On the other, they do promise change—the possibility of change, at least. Being able to envision the dismantling of the master’s house is the necessary initial step on the way to finding the right tools with which to do the job.

As with the quasi-hero worship that Gramsci himself is sometimes subjected to, it is hard to separate these two phrases from a certain romanticism—a mixture of melancholic angst and sublime defiance. I use the term deliberately: the 1857 speech in which Douglass uttered “Power concedes…” is one of the many times he also quoted a line from Lord Byron’s Childe Harold—“Who would themselves be free, must strike the blow.” (Here is another speech with the line.) As Ethan Kytle has argued, Byron’s poetry and romanticism generally inspired not only Douglass (whose surname was adapted from a Walter Scott hero), but also Harriet Beecher Stowe and many other antislavery activists, black and white, men and women.

In addition to Douglass’s own romanticism, those who use these phrases today also often invoke them somewhat romantically, treating them as a form of progressive positive thinking, as exhortations about will or energy rather than as poetic efforts to underline the structural difficulties of achieving justice. You just have to keep demanding! You just have to turn your back on the master’s tools! You’ll get there!

Organizing is, of course, brutally hard, and optimism of the will is not to be scoffed at. But the popular, romantic theory of change embodied in these two quotes is—particularly when they are marshalled as standalone admonitions—all too meager as a historical analysis. Yet this has not stopped even exceptionally clear-sighted historians from dropping into its shallow embrace from time to time.

The instance I’m thinking of at the moment comes from Samuel Moyn’s Not Enough: Human Rights in an Unequal World (Harvard, 2018), which I want to take a moment to talk about as a whole first before dialing in on a specific passage.

Not Enough is like all of Moyn’s work: a frontal assault on the lazy reader. His argumentation is so tight, so exacting, and yet his scope, his understanding of the stakes of his arguments and of the arguments with which he is engaging, is so formidably panoramic that I imagine it is very difficult—probably impossible—to get anything out of his work unless you have your entire mental apparatus deployed.

Not Enough tells a two-part story: first, how equality became a goal for state action through the emergence of the welfare state; and second, how that ideal was supplanted by sufficiency within a neoliberal (or, if that word chafes you, let’s say developmentalist) consensus. This story dovetails with Moyn’s previous work on human rights, as he demonstrates that the human rights movement that emerged in the 1970s melded with and mutually supported this new ideal of sufficiency as a universal goal of state and private action. Fortuitously, human rights and sufficiency created a package of moral and political idealism and action that seemed both comprehensively bold and yet efficiently operationalizable. The glamor of this package, Moyn concludes, drew the last shreds of attention away from the older ideal of equality, which was already—and for separate reasons—in full retreat.

That summary may be a bit opaque without a fuller explanation of the distinction Moyn draws between sufficiency and equality. One way to think about the difference is to contrast distributive and redistributive programs. To some extent, all distributive programs are redistributive—the something you give to person A either came from person B or could have gone to person B—but generally redistribution is not their purpose. Preferably, distributive programs do not substantially change the positions of the people or institutions from whom resources are drawn. Distributive programs are supposed to be, as the saying goes, “no skin off their back.” Redistributive programs, on the other hand, are supposed to change the overall map of where resources are located, moving some resources closer to some people and further away from others. It is as important that there be a ceiling on how much resources one person can hoard as it is that no one go entirely without resources.

Sufficiency, in other words, is entirely compatible with inequality—as long as everyone makes it over a certain minimum, it doesn’t matter how much the richest people have. Equality, however, presupposes material sufficiency, while also insisting that excessive concentration of wealth creates its own set of problems which also need to be addressed.

The history of these two ideals as Moyn tells it is both intricate and expansive: I was rapt while watching him connect one piece of his story to another. I was also grateful—as a framework, the contrast between sufficiency and equality has helped me greatly in some of my own scholarship. Yet if Moyn clearly and confidently tells a historical narrative about sufficiency replacing equality as the highest ideal of political action and moral aspiration, he seems more undecided about the strategic relation between the two concepts.

Moyn’s overall goal in the book is to convince readers that sufficiency is not a proper ultimate goal, in the sense that he views the history of the past forty years or so as a demonstration that when sufficiency is prioritized, inequality is unchecked or even encouraged. “[E]ven if it is entirely possible for those who care about sufficiency simply to prioritize it, insisting that they value equality as a postponed next step,” he writes, “it is far more common to believe that the goal of achieving sufficiency depends on embracing more inequality” (4). Inequality is, in a sense, a bribe that is paid to the very wealthy to induce them to try to solve global poverty through philanthropy or some other non-redistributive means. If one tries to fight inequality as well as deprivation, the implication goes, the very rich will simply withdraw their munificence: you will end up beating neither inequality nor poverty.

However, Moyn reconsiders and suggests that this may not be the case. Sure, the financial titans may withhold their charity in the face of egalitarianism, but “It might be that you have to strive at [a] more equal society even to get the most vital needs met,” he muses (5). Rather than trying to convince the wealthy that sufficiency is an achievable and worthwhile goal, frighten them into opening their wallets by bruiting a redistributive solution to poverty.

Almost at the end of the book, he returns to this suggestion that a more radical drive for equality is the only kind of demand that can secure sufficiency. He invokes the concept of “the reformism of fear,” a term that French theorist Pierre Rosanvallon introduced in his book The Society of Equals (2011; translated into English 2013) used to describe the kind of concessions made by conservative governments from Bismarck to Nixon to strengthen welfare and social rights. Yet in this scenario, the pressure was applied not only from below but also from outside.

It can be no accident that the era of relative material equality in the mid-twentieth century was also the age of totalitarian regimes and of the Cold War, which exacted an appalling toll on the world. National welfare built a floor of protection and [a] ceiling on inequality only in the presence of frightening internal and external threats—a prominent and well-organized labor movement and a communist menace, however magnified out of proportion… Governance expanded to secure material equality because the state was viewed as less frightening than the threats only it could stave off. By contrast, the human rights movement at its most inspiring has stigmatized governmental repression and violence, but it has never offered a functional replacement for the sense of fear that led to both protection and redistribution for those left alive by the horrors of the twentieth century. (219)

This argument resembles in some ways both Jefferson Cowie’s “Great Exception” thesis and Ira Katznelson’s story of the “Southern cage” surrounding the New Deal. In all three cases, the mid-century ascension of the welfare state (at least in the US) emerged in a symbiotic relationship with something unholy. For Cowie, the suppression of immigration after 1924 (among other factors) created the kind of working-class solidarity and sense of national cohesion that made “universal” (i.e., for whites) social programs seem both feasible and merited. For Katznelson, FDR and his Brain Trust took a gamble that keeping white Southern Democrats in the fold was a reasonable price to pay for the New Deal’s legislative progress, leaving Jim Crow for another day. And in Moyn’s case, the welfare state was a kind of by-blow of the brutal Soviet, fascist, and Chinese experiments in redistribution.

It is not hard to see why such narratives are being put forth in today’s political climate. All three suggest—even though the authors strive to forestall the implication—that the conditions which produced social democratic triumphs are either unrepeatable, undesirable, or both. That suits a certain spirit of romantic bleakness that one can find easily on Twitter (and many other places besides).

Yet it is possible, I think, to peel away a little the facts of the histories that Moyn, Katznelson, and Cowie have written from the psychological assumptions they make about their historical actors’ motivations and decisions. For instance, is “reformism of fear” really such a solid thesis to account for US or UK emulation of the kinds of central planning and robust social welfare they observed in totalitarian countries? Fear there was in abundance—of that there is no doubt. But is that all there was? Not envy or curiosity or admiration? Not competitiveness or inspiration?

Of course, we do have brilliant studies of transatlantic crosspollinations of reform driven by those kind of emotions, with Daniel Rodgers’s Atlantic Crossings and James Kloppenberg’s Uncertain Victory taking pride of place. But those are also histories where the master’s tools are precisely the instruments being taken up in the cause of reform, where power is looking for something to fix even before a demand is made.

Perhaps those histories did not sufficiently register the limitations imposed by using the master’s tools. I think that is a fair assessment, and I imagine that they would be written differently today. Yet there is a willingness to think beyond fear and force as the motivations for change that I still hope to hold onto, and that I think we must hold onto simply in order to be open to a wider range of human motivations in our sources. We need, I think, to be prepared to find optimism of the intellect as well as optimism of the will in our histories.

11 Thoughts on this Post

S-USIH Comment Policy

We ask that those who participate in the discussions generated in the Comments section do so with the same decorum as they would in any other academic setting or context. Since the USIH bloggers write under our real names, we would prefer that our commenters also identify themselves by their real name. As our primary goal is to stimulate and engage in fruitful and productive discussion, ad hominem attacks (personal or professional), unnecessary insults, and/or mean-spiritedness have no place in the USIH Blog’s Comments section. Therefore, we reserve the right to remove any comments that contain any of the above and/or are not intended to further the discussion of the topic of the post. We welcome suggestions for corrections to any of our posts. As the official blog of the Society of US Intellectual History, we hope to foster a diverse community of scholars and readers who engage with one another in discussions of US intellectual history, broadly understood.

  1. I think the post makes a good point. I’ve read Not Enough and had a (private) exchange with Moyn about it (roughly a year ago). I appreciated that he took the time to engage with some objections I raised, objections that dealt with certain aspects of the book not directly discussed in this post.

    Without rehashing all this in a blog comment box, I’ll say that the way Moyn sets up his narrative leads him, in my view, to some conceptual fuzziness about “equality,” notably in his treatment of the New Economic International Order. He acknowledges that the NIEO was about more equality between countries (i.e., between entire nation-states or entire societies), not about more equality between individuals. By contrast, the domestic welfare states in the West aimed at, to the extent they were redistributive, more equality between persons within a national society. In the book, both the NIEO and the redistributive Western welfare states are basically put on the “equality” side of the equality-vs.-sufficiency divide, even though their objects of concern (countries vs. individuals) were different.

    My sense is that Moyn’s treatment of the NIEO reflects some recent historiographical trends. (I say “my sense” b/c I have not had a chance to read most of the recent historical work on the NIEO, other than Moyn’s book.) I’m somewhat doubtful that the recent historiography adequately captures the way the NIEO was debated at the time, though I may be wrongly extrapolating from Moyn’s book to other recent treatments. Btw the NIEO generated a huge literature at the time, only a fraction of which Moyn cites and discusses in Not Enough (which is not necessarily a criticism, just a neutral statement of fact). For one discussion of some of this literature, see (a piece Moyn does not cite) Robert W. Cox’s review-essay “Ideologies and the New International Economic Order,” International Organization, v. 33 no. 2, Spring 1979.

    • Hi Louis,
      Thanks for your comment! I don’t know enough about the NIEO to really field your question adequately, but my sense of the chapter in Not Enough was that Moyn saw the organization as an attempt to reground social rights conceptually and practically in something other than the nation-state. So while the process of equalization would be focused on inequalities among different states (North vs. South or the West and the Rest), the process of redistribution would actually be administered by institutions that existed above or outside of individual nation-states.

      I think Moyn’s thinking there was largely shaped by the work of Adom Getachew, whose new book Worldmaking after Empire I haven’t read but looks very impressive. Someone should review it for the blog! (Hint?)

      • Andy,
        Thanks for the reply. Getachew’s book looks interesting and perhaps I will take up your hint.

  2. P.s. This is not the place for a long discussion of the NIEO, but just wanted to add re: “the process of redistribution would actually be administered by institutions that existed above or outside of individual nation-states” — partly. The NIEO in its most concrete form was a set of demands/proposals; some of these involved institutions above or outside the state while others did not. The NIEO generated tons of paper, but the most basic document, the NIEO Declaration adopted (with by the 6th Special Session of the UN General Assembly in 1974, is fairly short and is available online:
    http://www.un-documents.net/s6r3201.htm

    • correction — should read: “adopted (without a formal vote) by the 6th Special Session” etc.

  3. Andy, this is great; I’m definitely going to be reading Not Enough now. (As a side note, it’s interesting how this phrase “not enough” is going around, seeing how I used it in my own book title! :p)

    I have one question though; what do you mean when you say “where power is looking for something to fix even before a demand is made”? I’m not familiar with Uncertain Victory but my general impression of progressivism (in relation to Atlantic Crossings) is that it very much was responding to a demand; from the left, from the working-class, that predates most of their theories and efforts at reform by at least a few decades. The Communist Manifesto, after all, is 1848.

  4. Robin Marie,
    Andy obviously can speak for himself, but my two cents on the question you raise would be to disagree somewhat with your premise. Reformers of one stripe or another, and that includes some politicians once they are in power, may respond to external demands but can also be moved partly by their own moral compasses, their internal, so to speak, sense of what they want to accomplish. People are complicated, and the crassest electoral calculations and power plays can coexist with idealistic impulses in the same politician. I think a case can be made that that statement applies in the cases of, to take just a few examples, FDR, LBJ (despite their obvious flaws), and, probably more clearly, Clement Attlee, who was p.m. during the initial expansion of the postwar British welfare state.

    In the case of U.S. Progressivism, my impression is that many of its adherents were not only responding to working-class demands but were middle or upper-class reformers responding to their own convictions. So my reading of the phrase “before a demand is made” in the phrase at issue is that it refers to the immediate context of actions and convictions, and not to, say, whether the Progressives’ interests in, for example, more direct democracy or safer working conditions were anticipated by programmatic statements in the Communist Manifesto or elsewhere.

      • Regretted that line after I posted, but blog comments aren’t always as polished as one might like. Anyway, it wasn’t intended as an “explanation.” (Your book”s on my to-read list btw.)

  5. Hi Robin Marie,
    “Demand” is the wrong word. I meant something stronger, more like “where power is looking for something to fix even before its hand is forced.” And that criterion is, I think, subjective, both for the historian and for the historical actor. Many historical actors do not accurately perceive how close they are to reaching a point where inaction is more dangerous to their self-interests than action, and the historian’s hindsight isn’t always 20/20 either–there may be reasonable disagreements among historians about which or how many options were available to a historical actor in a given moment, or when the “point of no return” was reached.

    My point is that in some cases, powerful historical actors have chosen to share power or redistribute resources even when they are in a position where they feel that their self-interests are not yet at risk, when they could conceivably hold out for longer and wait for some exogenous factor to occur that will give them an advantage–for the tide to turn, so to speak. Sometimes this is–as Louis notes–because of their moral compasses, sometimes it is (as with Bismarck, I think, and with many welfare capitalists of the early 20th century) because they believe that resolving some conflict with the less powerful now will give them some advantage over their competitors (other firms or nations), and sometimes they will share power or redistribute resources because they have been convinced that doing so will result in a more functional (more prosperous, more stable) system overall. They could be convinced about that because there are alternative economic or social models that they admire, or they could be convinced by arguments from within their own society.

    Let me be more concrete, though. The above possibilities are all, I think, potential answers to the question: why did liberal and center-right governments as well as big business in the United States and western Europe accept some degree of economic planning as necessary during and after World War II–to the extent that they did? (I haven’t gotten as far as I would like to in Larry Glickman’s new book, but I’m anticipating that he demonstrates how limited that acceptance of economic planning was among big businesses. Still, I think it remains the case that there was some acceptance.) I’m not convinced that the reformism of fear is a complete or even very accurate answer to that question, and I think it’s critical that we get a good answer.

    To round back to your original question, the reason I used the word demand was because it was Douglass’s word. But there’s a great deal of flexibility in how we should read his admonition: does he mean “demand” to include physical force or the threat of violence? In context, I think that’s implicit, but “demand” can also be read more gently to include various kinds of public demonstrations or even forms of political non-resistance.

    • Hi Andy —

      Thanks for that clarification! I agree, obviously, that these questions lay in those grey zones where historians can reasonably disagree; I also don’t doubt that genuinely good people exist in all times and places, and therefore the existence of that decency cannot be completely excluded from historical causes. But being the crass materialist I am, I do error on the side of the power struggle, as I’m sure you know :). To paraphrasing Kenneth Clark, he said something to the extent that a cause needs to be both righteous and compelling to the powerful; ie, both moral truth and a risk to run if it is ignored have to be present. I think that’s a useful way of thinking about it.

      Louis — It’s alright. Just maybe keep in mind that certain things can be taken for granted among colleagues. 😉

Comments are closed.